Alexandre Lefebvre鈥檚 Liberalism as a Way of Life belongs to the school of Anglo-American political philosophy whose defining figure was Harvard鈥檚 John Rawls, author of A Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism. The Rawls school views the pursuit of justice as the cornerstone of a liberal society. But Lefebvre鈥檚 insightful account is also something of a departure, an original and at times exciting contribution to our understanding of liberalism鈥攊n the classical as opposed to the partisan political sense.
A professor at the University of Sydney, Lefebvre describes himself as a 鈥渓iberal all the way down.鈥� For him, as for Rawls, in deciding on laws and social arrangements that can perpetuate a just society, we must place ourselves behind a 鈥渧eil of ignorance鈥� in 鈥渢he original position鈥� of a member without attributes of such a society鈥攖hat is, without knowledge of one鈥檚 place in it, whether one is rich or poor, favorably endowed with genetic and environmental gifts or encumbered by their absence. From this position, Rawls argues, reasonable people鈥攌nowing nothing about where they would fall in such a society鈥攚ould write its rules in such a way as to favor the least advantaged among them, because once the veil is lifted, they could find they occupy exactly the least advantaged position.
No society has ever been created from such a premise, of course, and from a certain angle, it could look as if Rawls was rejecting all claims of justice on behalf of societies鈥攐r nation-states鈥攖hat fail his test of putting the least advantaged first. Thus, one could read Rawls鈥攁nd many did鈥攁s calling for radical reform and repudiating the legitimacy of states organized according to other priorities. But that鈥檚 not how Rawls saw it. His liberal theory of justice didn鈥檛 encompass a corresponding theory of injustice, according to which all societies reflecting deviations from reasonable conclusions behind the veil of ignorance were so disconnected from justice as to warrant condemnation. He thought they could improve.
In any event, Lefebvre notes, Rawls himself became somewhat dissatisfied with A Theory of Justice鈥攏otwithstanding its colossal success in his field and its standing as perhaps the most influential work of political philosophy of our time ever since its publication in 1971鈥攐n the grounds that it was 鈥渦nrealistic.鈥� So he turned to another question in his later work, Political Liberalism (1993). 鈥淗ow is it possible,鈥� Rawls asked, 鈥渇or there to exist over time a just and stable society of free and equal citizens, who remain profoundly divided by reasonable religious, philosophical, and moral doctrines?鈥�
The answer is that competing but reasonable 鈥渃omprehensive doctrines鈥� at work among people could yield to a 鈥渓iberal political conception鈥� in which big-picture doctrines would be respected insofar as they were reasonable. For Rawls, a comprehensive doctrine is anything that spells out the details of how to live a good life: as an Orthodox Jew, say, or an Opus Dei Catholic, or a Communist, or a cultivator of Aristotelian virtue. Political liberalism would never seek that status of a 鈥渃omprehensive doctrine,鈥� but it could be the organizing and limiting principle according to which adherents of various doctrines could live in a stable society of free and equal citizens.
Lefebvre writes about Rawls鈥檚 evolution as a thinker very well. But his distinctive achievement is to note that nowadays Rawls needs turning around. That鈥檚 because, he says, 鈥渄ecade by decade, year by year, and day by day, liberal ideals and sensibilities have spread to every nook and cranny of the background culture of liberal democracies.鈥� Further, 鈥渟o ubiquitous is liberalism that it has performed that special trick of disappearance achieved only by omnipresence: to have become invisible by infiltrating everything.鈥� Lefebvre鈥檚 conclusion: 鈥淟ove it or hate it, we all swim鈥攚e positively marinate鈥攊n liberal waters. And here is my critique: the firewall that political liberalism draws between comprehensive doctrines and a liberal political conception obscures this changed landscape.鈥� Lefebvre doesn鈥檛 quite say that liberalism has become a 鈥渃omprehensive doctrine,鈥� indeed the defining comprehensive doctrine, of modern democracies. But he ought to have.
It is true that liberalism offers no single formula for how to live a good life of the sort that once characterized states and their gods or ideologies. In that sense, it is not 鈥渃omprehensive,鈥� leaving to individual judgment or conscience many important questions about how to live. But liberalism does include at least one doctrinal element that overrides any and all presumptions of any and all comprehensive doctrines that might contradict it. That is the 鈥渞easonableness standard.鈥� Liberals insist that adherents of comprehensive doctrines, whether they count themselves liberal or not, be 鈥渞easonable鈥� in their adherence. Indeed, the word is central to Rawls鈥檚 research question鈥攕o much so that one could say he slipped his answer into the question itself. An unreasonable 鈥渃omprehensive doctrine鈥濃攖hat is, a coercive or violent doctrine鈥攃annot be part of a 鈥渏ust and stable society of free and equal citizens.鈥� It is up to these contending comprehensive doctrines, almost all of which have historical associations with coercion and violent propagation, to modify themselves as necessary to become 鈥渞easonable.鈥� Whether their adherents profess allegiance or opposition to a liberal political conception, their behavior must conform to it, or there will be adverse consequences for them.
Lefebvre has the acuity to see that, generally speaking, the behavior of individuals and organized groups in modern democratic societies is liberalism-compliant. He addresses his book mainly to those who identify themselves as through-and-through liberals in the sense of both the Rawls of A Theory of Justice and the Rawls of Political Liberalism鈥� people who are, if not 鈥渓iberals all the way down鈥� like himself, then most of the way. Unfortunately, this nudges him into two related observational errors. As Peter Berkowitz notes, Lefebvre is too stingy in recognizing the genuineness of the liberalism of people who, for whatever reason, don鈥檛 identify themselves as liberals. As an exercise, Lefebvre would like liberals to imagine themselves in the 鈥渙riginal position鈥� when thinking about the fair distribution of social goods. That might be sufficient for a certain subset of liberals of the left-progressive sort, but if those were the only people practicing 鈥渓iberalism as a way of life,鈥� there would be no book to write about a society imbued with liberalism. The point is that most conservatives, most Orthodox and other Jews, most devout conservative and liberal Catholics, most evangelical Protestants, and many other non-progressives in Western societies, are nevertheless practicing liberals in daily life. They follow their 鈥渃omprehensive doctrines鈥� in a reasonable way鈥攚hich is to say, within the overriding noncoercive liberal comprehensive doctrine. Although it may be tough for those steeped in the ways of Anglo-American political philosophy to accept, even the vast majority of Trump supporters are functionally liberal鈥攏ot those who stormed the Capitol or those who think storming capitols is a good idea, but most everyone else. It may also be tough for people who spend their lives theorizing politics to accept that many Americans and other denizens of modern society don鈥檛 care very much about politics at all, and that鈥檚 fine.
His second observational miscue lies in his characterization of the gap between liberalism as the pursuit of justice or fairness and the actuality of the liberal world we live in. Rawlsian justice is what 鈥渓iberals all the way down鈥� want; but 鈥渓iberaldom,鈥� in Lefebvre鈥檚 coinage, is what we (all of us, whether we want it or not) actually have. The liberalism of liberaldom falls far short of what sweet reason would yield behind the veil of ignorance. In his own characterization, Lefebvre鈥檚 liberaldom is to liberalism as Kierkegaard鈥檚 鈥淐hristendom鈥� is to Christianity鈥攁 complacent world in which we are all failures unable to live up to our professed ideals. In his view, liberals in liberaldom have much to answer for. He admits that he and his wife 鈥渟pend a lot of money to send our daughter to private school鈥� for the additional opportunity it provides, even though that might betray the egalitarianism required by Rawls鈥檚 conception of justice. 鈥淣ow it鈥檚 your turn鈥� to start your self-help program by making your own necessary admissions, he admonishes his liberal readers.
That is refreshingly honest, even though what such admissions really serve to illuminate is a key problem with Rawls鈥檚 approach to the pursuit of justice鈥攚hich is that we will always strive to do more for those we love and who are in our own personal care, and that there is nothing unjust or immoral in that. Lefebvre is accordingly a little too hard on himself and on liberalism as we live it.
Enjoyed this article? Subscribe to Hudson鈥檚 newsletters to stay up to date with our latest content.